Copyright: Janet Cameron |
Art is gratuitous, demands our attention and does not require us to theorise about it.
Are
criticism and evaluation relevant to works of art in the same way
that they are relevant to, for example, ethics or morality?
Stuart Hampshire, in his essay "Logic and Appreciation"
believes that it is possible to be consistent with regard to ethics,
which, he says: "...are needed to meet common human
predicaments."
Art,
on the other hand, he regards as individual and unrepeatable and from
this, he concludes: "One does not need a formula or a recipe
unless one needs repetitions." This seems fair comment. Why
should there be a formula for evaluation if the object in questions
is not in competition with any other similar object? As Hampshire
asserts, art is about the particular, and there is no limit to the
number of beautiful things that are specific and not in need of
generalisation.
Art
is Gratuitous
On
the other hand, art is gratuitous, demands our attention, and does
not ask us to theorise about it This doesn't mean we may not prefer
one work to another, admits Hampshire, but we do not need to grade
artworks one against another. "The critic may reject the work
done without being required to show what the artist ought to have
done..." However, moralists are expected to decide what
should have been done in place of a condemned action.
The
critic is not a judge, but a spectator of the object, "exactly
as it is," and "precisely this unique object... individual
and unrepeatable." Stuart Hampshire allows that the critic may
be analytical, helping people to perceive certain features that lead
them to appreciate what they are observing. The difficulty is when
the spectator-critic observes certain features as good, and then
tries to proclaim other works good for displaying the same features.
"Then," says Hampshire," "one looks away from the
particular qualities of the particular thing."
Moving
from the Particular to the General
The
originality discovered from an arrangement of elements "may bear
little analogy to originality found elsewhere." Yet, can
this argument be a valid means of defending Hampshire's position? To
say something is original is already to compare it to previous works,
and further, to find that it contains something new and different.
To make choices and exclusions involves grading. This necessarily
involves comparison and evaluation, even though the work remains as
it is, with its own particular features.
Monroe
Beardsley's Criteria for Evaluating Artworks
Monroe
Beardsley, as quoted in Colin Lyas' essay "The Evaluation of
Art" defines three general criteria of merit in evaluating an
artwork. These are: "unity, complexity and intensity." If
the hearer or reader of the work can be persuaded to agree that the
work displays one or more of these qualities, then the claim is
proved by a general rule that there is something good about the work.
Other descriptions, such as "it is humorous," or "it
is graceful," might be apt descriptions of the work, but they do
not necessarily show that it is good, unless linked to the basic
criteria set out above. If they cannot be linked, it may be that
there is something wrong about the work.
Stuart
Hampshire says, "The common vocabulary obstructs any
disinterested perceptions of things." Beardsley appears to
demonstrate this failing. Colin Lyas points out that what is not art
may still have unity, and art may have unity that is not necessarily
aesthetic. A painting that has a unity in pale colours may be
seen as insipid and banal." The same argument can be made
against intensity and complexity; they may show ugliness. Monroe
Beardsley's attempt to form general principles upon which to base
value judgments fails due to the inadequacy of his premises.
The
Critic Should Help Us to See, Hear and Feel
In
his essay, Colin Lyas says we cannot deduce an aesthetic description
from a non-aesthetic quality. Discrimination and judgement in the
arts is a matter of perception, which is a point also emphasised by
Hampshire. As Lyas says, "If, in seeking an ability to
discriminate aesthetically, we are seeking to see, hear and feel,
then it is difficult to see how proof or demonstration... can be any
part of what we want from criticism...all the critic can do is help
us to see something she or he has seen by directing our attention..."
However,
Hampshire is convinced that creative feeling that produces truly
individual aesthetic experience with its particularities defies value
judgements. He says, "Where the logician's framework of problem
and conclusion does not apply, the notion of "reason" loses
some of its meaning also; it is unnatural to ask: "Why is that
picture or sonata good?"
Evaluation
is Inevitable and Inescapable
Yet,
we all evaluate films, books, music and plays that we experience.
It is natural.
A critic should evaluate
particular works, for instance:
-
When a new novel appears, critics should try to say whether it is any good.
-
Evaluation is inevitable. If a critic perceives and then discusses the aesthetic qualities of a work, some kind of evaluation is inescapable.
-
Surely the critic must use some ordinary language, for example: "Hamlet is indecisive" or "Lady Macbeth pressures Macbeth into killing the King."
I
remember once, going to a private garden party. One of the band stood
up and made an announcement. "I have to say," he said,
"that comparisons are odious. Even so, I just want to say the
young lady in the trouser suit stands out above all the others."
It was true. The rest of us were in our standard jeans and T-shirts
and, there she was, stunning in contrast, in a flecked tweed trouser
suit with a tailored jacket and sharp, creased pants.
Odious
or not, comparisons are here to stay. It's our nature.
Sources:
Hampshire,
Stuart, "Logic and Appreciation," Art,
Context and Value, Ed:
Stuart Sim, The Open University, 1992.
Lyas,
Colin, "The Evaluation of Art," Philosophical
Aesthetics,
Blackwell Publishers in Association with The Open University, 1992.
No comments:
Post a Comment