Mona Lisa by Leonardo da Vinci |
The terms
'necessary condition' and 'sufficient condition' are used to attempt to define
the qualities that make a work of art. A 'necessary condition' is a quality
without which the work would not meet the requirement of being judged 'art'. It
should apply, in common, to all works that are described as art. For example, X
is a necessary condition of Y if, and only if, Y cannot be without X.
A 'feeling' is not a 'necessary condition of art, says the philospher, Oswald Hanfling,
"...someone may create a work of art, say a beautiful vase, without any
intention of passing on feelings he has lived through."
'Sufficient
condition' specifies a quality that may be defined as follows:
X is a
'sufficient condition' of Y, if X, by itself, guarantees Y. In other words, a
'sufficient condition' is present in a work of art and is sufficient in itself
to justify the label of art. If the quality is not sufficient, this could be
because this quality may also be present in other artefacts or works of nature
that are not art. Hanfling asks if 'beauty' can be considered a 'sufficient
condition' of art and concludes that it cannot.
"No, for many natural
objects, scenery, etc. are beautiful without being works of art."
Hanfling looks
at a quality shown by W. Tatarkiewicz, which considers the effect of art on the
receipient: "...capable of evoking delight or emotion or shock. Hanfling
says this cannot stand as a 'sufficient condition' because:
"...if fond
parents take photographs of their children, these may be capable of producing
delight... it would not follow they were works of art."
The Historicist Fallacy
The Historicist Fallacy
The philosopher, Monroe Beardsley, questions the 'historicist fallacy' - that philosophy cannot judge past
societies or epochs in modern terms. The 'historicist fallacy' is that art
means no more than how a given historical period conceives it to be, which
leads to the 'radical relativist" view that no conceptual scheme is better
than any other. "But, evolving a better literary theory... than they had,
would not prevent us from grasping their beliefs."
He argues that once
people thought whales were fish, but that this does not prevent us from
studying the early stages of the whaling industry. He says, "What we want
to understand... is what is going on?"
Beardsley's Key Presuppositions
Beardsley's
first meta-aesthetic is that aesthetic theory "... should mark a
distinction that is theoretically significant." Secondly, "...that in
selecting key terms for aesthetic theory, we ought to stay as close as
convenient to ordinary use." Beardsley's third meta-aesthetic condition is
that artwork "...should be of the greatest possible utility to inquirers
in other fields besides aesthetics" and especially in the fields of art
history and anthropology. Fourthly, he believes that "...art and the
aesthetic should be conceptually linked."
Beardsley's
necessary condition for art is that it should be an aesthetic experience. His
sufficient conditions are that it is either "...an arrangement of
conditions intended to be capable of affording an experience with marked
aesthetic character, or belonging to a type of arrangement typically intended
to have this capacity."
In conclusion,
the key presuppositions of Beardsley's theory are as follows:
·
A work of art must be an aesthetic
experience where participation is active and searching.
·
It is not necessary that the artist's
intention was to produce a work of art. Art can be produced by creating
religious artefacts, for instance. He states, regarding the painters of Lascaux
who probably did not know they were producing art, "But it does not follow
that they were not producing art."
·
Other periods and cultures can be judged
using modern theory in the context of their own beliefs.
Sources:
·
Beardsley, Monroe C, "Redefining
Art" Theories of Art and
Beauty, The Open University, 1991.
·
Hanfling, Oswald, 'The Problem of
Definition' Philosophical
Aesthetics, Blackwell
Publishers, 1992.
No comments:
Post a Comment