Christ and the Disciples at Emmaus |
The
philosopher Alfred Lessing says: “Considering a work of art
aesthetically superior because it is genuine, or inferior because it
is forged, has little or nothing to do with aesthetic judgement or
criticism. It is, rather, a piece of snobbery.” Lessing maintains
that “Pure aesthetics cannot explain forgery,” and that
“...genuineness versus forgery is a non-aesthetic standard of
judgement.”
Arthur
Koestler, in demonstrating the intrinsic value of pure aesthetics,
uses as an example the forgeries of the Gothic wall paintings by
Lothar
Malskat,
who was hired by Dietrich Fey to restore the Lubeck frescoes in 1948.
He supplemented them with paintings of his own, subsequently
provoking a counterfeit scandal. When the forgeries were discovered,
the paintings ceased to be valuable. Koestler asks: “…whether the
Lubeck saints are less beautiful… because they had been painted by
Herr Malskat and not by somebody else.” The key point of Koestler’s
argument is: “…the principal mark of genius is not perfection,
but originality, the opening of new frontiers; once this is done, the
conquered territory becomes common property.”
The
Vermeer Forgery “Christ and the Disciples at Emmaus" by Van
Meegeren
Alfred
Lessing claims that the Vermeer forgery Christ and the Disciples at Emmaus by Van Meegeren is a work of beauty. “The matter of genuineness
versus forgery is but another non-aesthetic standard of judgement,”
he says. He relegates the painting’s non-aesthetic authenticity to
the same level as other non-aesthetic criteria, such as “biography”
and “history of art,” etc.
The
fact that a painting is a forgery may not detract from its pure
aesthetic value in the common understanding of a work of beauty, but
it is open to criticism due to what it may lack as a piece of
deception, taken out of its historical and biographical context.
Lessing describes the matter of originality as “a certain
superficial individuality, which serves to distinguish it from all
other works of art.”
Arthur
Koestler agrees with Lessing that exact reproductions of existing
paintings are not necessarily undermined merely because a painting is
a forgery. However, Oswald Hanfling points out that the Van Meegeren
forgeries, were not exact reproductions, but were: “in the style of
Vermeer” and were of subjects different from those painted by
Vermeer.” This suggests that the aesthetic value of the forgeries
could be enhanced by aspects of originality.
The
Contribution of the Perceiver
However,
Nelson Goodman says that it is not enough to rely upon the act of
merely looking. He uses the analogy of twins, who, initially look the
same, but over time show perceptible differences. Further, the “now”
of looking affects future looking. He says that he sees, “The
present looking as a role of training.” Goodman believes the
acceptance of a forgery as an original may colour the spectator’s
understanding of an artist’s work. Even with these qualifications,
Goodman claims that this does not prove the original is better than
the forgery: “…a copy of a Lastman
by
Rembrandt may well be better than the original.”
For
some critics, the ontology of the work and its originality add to its
appreciation and therefore, to its aesthetic value Goodman’s assertion allows for the participation of the perceiver:
“The aesthetic properties of a picture include not only those found
by looking at it, but also those that determine how it is to be
looked at.” If the perceiver’s contribution to the aesthetic
value of a painting is admitted, it is a small step further to accept
that he or she will bring their own understanding to the experience,
as a valid contribution.
A
Preference for Originality is not Snobbery
Oswald
Hanfling asks: “But is it right to exclude such qualities as
achievement and originality from the domain of aesthetic qualities
and aesthetic appreciation?” (It should be pointed out, however,
that this could also mean that snobbery may occur, when the perceiver
is impressed by the label of greatness and lacks the knowledge or
sensibility to discern.) Hanfling questions why these factors of
achievement and originality should not make us value an authentic
work above a forgery. “We may also be affected by the sheer
antiquity of a work, or by knowledge about its original functions,
for example, in a religious context.”
The
Disciples at Emmaus – a Lack of Artistic Integrity
Lessing’s
argument employs a narrower concept of the “aesthetic” which does
not do justice to our natural response to, and assessment of, art,
including originality. On the other hand, Lessing admits that there
is a further consideration which is nothing to do with snobbery, that
is, the issue of deception: “It seems to me … it is not so much
against the spirit of beauty (aesthetics) as against the spirit of
art. Somehow, a work such as 'The Disciples' lacks artistic
integrity.”
Following
on from this is Oswald Hanfling’s point that forgery on a large
scale: “…may distort our knowledge of art history.” To object
to deception or fraud, which, after all, may have far-reaching
effects on our understanding of art history, cannot be labelled as
snobbery. It is a natural human response.
Oswald
Hanfling, in giving us a broader notion of the aesthetic, also shows
that a preference for the original is not necessarily based on
snobbery.
Sources:
-
“Art and Authenticity,” Nelson Goodman, Art, Context and Value, edited by Stuart Sim, The Open University, 1992.
-
“Aesthetic Qualities,” Osward Hanfling, Philosophical Aesthetics, edited by Oswald Hanfling, Blackwell Publishers in Association with The Open University, 1992.
-
“The Act of Creation,” Arthur Koestler, Art, Context and Value, edited by Stuart Sim, The Open University, 1992.
-
“What is Wrong with a Forgery?” Alfred Lessing, Art, Context and Value, edited by Stuart Sim, The Open University, 1992.
No comments:
Post a Comment